This blog is maintained by academics at the Scottish Centre for Crime and Justice Research who use this space to comment and respond to crime and justice news and developments. To find out more about who we are and what we do please visit www.sccjr.ac.uk.







Wednesday, 24 March 2010

"Ugly criminals"?

Cross-posted from What's Left of Reason

"Being very attractive reduces a young adult’s propensity for criminal activity and being unattractive increases it. Being very attractive is also positively associated with wages and with adult vocabulary test scores, which implies that beauty may have an impact on human capital formation. The results suggest that a labour market penalty provides a direct incentive for unattractive individuals toward criminal activity. The level of beauty in high school is associated with criminal propensity seven to eight years later, which seems to be due to the impact of beauty in high school on human capital formation, although this avenue seems to be effective for females only" (Mocan and Tekin 2010).I want to use this post to discuss a recent paper that appeared in The Review of Economics and Statistics (full version here if you can access it, otherwise the abstract above will have to do). Initially because I though the idea was so mad it was worth a few comments, but having re-read the paper more now because I think it throws up some very interesting points beyond its specific empirical content.The article is based on analysis of the US National Longitudinal Study of Adolescent Health (n=15,338, which is relevant). It uses respondent’s ‘beauty’ (controlling for a very wide range of other variables) to predict self-reported criminal behaviour. It’s worth noting that the mechanisms the paper suggests for attractiveness affecting criminal activity are all social – it essentially claims that the less attractive are more likely to commit crime (and the more attractive less likely) because they are treated differently by those around them, in terms of access to the jobs market, treatment at school, and so forth (hence for example the lower vocabulary scores mentioned above - it's not that 'ugly' people are thick, its that they get treated differently at school and this inhibits their learning process). Methods and statsFirst, let’s get the methods/statistics out of the way. With two provisos they are actually quite convincing. It really does seem that the physical attractiveness of females (although to a lesser extent males – see below) is associated with self-reported criminal activity, in the ways suggested in the abstract above.The two provisos are quite important, though. Firstly, how is physical attractiveness measured? It turns out by the interviewers in the survey. There is something immediately almost repellent about this, but the authors present some evidence that such ratings are fairly robust, and I don’t want to get bogged down in this point, so let’s just take it as read for now that they do have a somewhat accurate measure of the survey respondent’s physical attractiveness.The second proviso is even more important. Namely, that the effect sizes they identify are very small. For example, “Being a very attractive female reduces the propensity to damage property by 1.1 percentage points” (controlling for personal and family characteristics). This effect is statistically significant, because of the very large sample size. But is it substantively meaningful? Does it make any sense to concentrate on such a small effect? The authors clearly think so, and up to a point I agree with them – the social world is a complicated place, and the unique association between any one factor (e.g. physical attractiveness) and another (e.g. propensity to vandalise things) is almost bound to be small. If there is a statistically significant association, robust to all the control variables that seem relevant, it probably does mean something.But on the other hand, there must come a point where an association, although significant, is so small that it really can’t have much meaning – certainly if we want to change the world in some way. A one percentage point difference is interesting in the context of this paper, but would be so if, for example, some sort of policy intervention was being planned? I think we as social scientists do not pay enough attention to the pay off between statistical significance and effect size, and this paper butts right up against that point.One other point on the specific empirical content – as noted the effect of ‘attractiveness’ on crime appear much more consistent for women than for men. I’m not too sure what to make of this, and neither I think are the authors. While it might be consistent with their theoretical framework (since it appears physical attractiveness as rated by others varies by more among women than among men, it should therefore have a bigger effect), it’s unclear how this fits with ‘explaining crime’, given the well known gender disproportionality in criminal activity.Three more substantive pointsThere are (at least) three more substantive points I’d like to make about the paper, again because these seem to me to be relevant far beyond its specific content (there are more but these particularly strike me).First is the rational choice theory model of criminal behaviour used in the paper. It essentially takes as a given the idea that people commit crimes when there is motive (reward) to do so, there is an opportunity, and the rewards outweigh the potential costs. Yet much recent work on why people commit crime would stress the importance of morals and normative values – to the extent that most people do not commit crime because they do not even see it as an option, even in situations where they would gain from doing so.Now, this may not make much difference in terms of this specific paper, because we would expect normative orientations toward the law to be evenly distributed across ‘attractive’ and ‘unattractive’ people and thus not affect the results. But taking such a narrowly instrumentalist approach toward decisions to commit crime does I think in the wider context run the risk of over-simplifying what seems certain to be a very complex process.More serious for the specific claims of the paper is its very one-sided view of what crime is. The types of crimes covered by the analysis are ‘damage’ (vandalism), burglary, robbery, theft, assault and selling drugs; essentially, ‘crimes of the poor’. What about white collar crime? Tax evasion? Fraud? Corporate crime? At the very least the omission of a wider range of criminal behaviour limits the claims that can be made by the paper. But worse, it may be that being physical attractive, and thus preferred in the job market to others, opens up greater opportunity to engage in white collar crime (by increasing both opportunity and level of potential gain). So it could be in these cases physical attractiveness is linked to higher rates of self-reported offending. Of course, such a impoverished of crime is not unique to this paper – it seems to bedevil many economic and similar approaches to criminological matters.But to finish on a more positive note I think this is a very interesting paper not because of the specific claims it makes but because of the way it tries to integrate ‘innate’ characteristic (physical attractiveness), personal proclivities and propensities (to commit crime), and the social world which influences and interacts with them. That is, it takes seriously the idea that people are individuals (and individual), and make personal choices about how and when to act – but their individuality and their choices (and possibility of choices) are structured and limited by the actions of others around them and the social and economic structures in which all are embedded. It seems to me that this kind of empirically robust ‘cross-level’ analysis is exactly the kind of thing we should be trying do more of in British criminology.

Friday, 19 March 2010

Stage 2 of the Criminal Justice and Licensing Bill Scotland

The amendments added at Stage 2 to the Bill are a cause for concern as they accelerate a trend of over criminalization and penalization in Scotland. Some of us have submitted more detailed comments on the mechanics of specific amendments, but in this brief statement we at the SCCJR are writing to express our consensus that these amendments, taken together, would make for an unwieldy, unevidenced and over complicated law. Enacting these amendments will create pressures to divert scarce resources into the justice system and thereby undermine the current strategies for securing community safety.

Additionally, by deleting the sections relating to the principles of sentencing, watering down the sentencing council proposals of the Scottish Prisons Commission, hardening the approach to breaches of bail and police undertakings, defining serious and organised crime so broadly, Scotland is not only losing its chance to do something progressive and bold in realising a more effective justice system, but it is adopting a reactionary stance to come up with a law that almost certainly will lead to net widening, penal expansion and worsening rates of reoffending.

Just as America, the world’s most aggressive user of prisons, has begun to recognise the error of its ways in the face of a fiscal crisis caused by penal expansion , Scotland would take up such discredited practices as mandatory minimum sentences; imprisonment as the main strategy of managing breaches of bail, probation and parole; and wide ranging criminalization of behaviour much of which is already prosecutable under common law or existing legislation. The amendments to the law hence appear to us to lack foundation in evidence or logic.

We also raise a separate concern about the procedure by which these amendments were made. The amendments proposed here introduce a number of new offences (in particular on stalking, engaging in paid-for sexual activity and related offences, voyeurism etc). Irrespective of the general questions of whether or not these are appropriate areas for criminalization, we are particularly concerned that these amendments are introducing major new elements to the Bill at Stage 2. There is thus no opportunity for proper debate or thorough scrutiny of either the amendments individually or the Bill as a revised whole. The proper procedure for introducing such offences should be in a stand-alone piece of legislation or at a much earlier stage in the legislative process. As things stand there is a risk that the democratic process is being subverted. Our concern, therefore, is that this Bill is becoming increasingly poor law. For this reason we would strongly urge that the amendments introducing new offences be removed from the draft Bill and presented to Parliament in separate legislation.

The Bill as originally introduced proposed reforms to sentencing based on a review of Scottish penal policy which included a widescale review of the empirical evidence related to the impact of sentencing on the prison population and put forward proposals on the basis of this evidence. The reforms proposed were a coherent package which sought to implement these proposals. We are concerned that the proposed amendments not only dilute the original proposals, but run the risk of replacing a principled and coherent approach to penal policy with just the kind of muddled and incoherent approach to sentencing that was identified as having created the problem for penal policy. This cannot be the most appropriate way to reduce re-offending and secure safer communities in Scotland.

Wednesday, 10 March 2010

Mandatory prison sentences for carrying knives

SCCJR’s Neil Hutton (Centre for Sentencing Research, Strathclyde University) and Fergus McNeill (University of Glasgow) recently submitted evidence to the Scottish Parliament Justice Committee. Their comments below concern amendments 10 and 10A to the Criminal Justice and Licensing (Scotland) Bill, which propose mandatory prison sentences for carrying knives.

  1. The assumption underpinning both of these amendments is presumably that the proposed minimum sentences will act as a deterrent to those who might consider carrying knives. If this assumption is correct, then the incidence of knife crime would decrease. However, while many people believe that criminal sentences have a deterrent effect, there is no evidence to support this. A recent authoritative review of the international research literature by the former Director of the Cambridge Institute of Criminology, Professor Michael Tonry, concludes that there is little credible evidence that changes in sanctions affect crime rates. For example, neither the Californian three strikes legislation nor the zero tolerance policing project in New York, both of which were claimed to demonstrate reductions in crime, had no significant impact on criminal behaviour. In New York, the decline in crime rates which occurred had begun four years previously (1990-91) and continued through the process of the zero tolerance policing project and did so across the USA (where quite different policing policies were being pursued) and not just in New York.
  2. Though it may seem counter-intuitive to suggest that the threat of sanctions does not exercise much influence on criminal behaviour, it is in fact relatively easy to see why this is the case. For punishment to have a deterrent effect on behaviour, certain conditions need to be met. The first of these is certainty: the prospective offender needs to believe that there is a very high chance of being apprehended. The second is celerity: the punishment needs to be immediate. The third is severity: the offender must experience the punishment as a significant ‘pain’ to be avoided. The fourth is intelligibility: the offender has to see the pain of the punishment as flowing (more or less automatically and immediately) from the behaviour. It is for all of these reasons that, for example, human beings learn very quickly not to place their hands in a fire. However, The reality is that none of these conditions can be applied in relation to sentencing for knife crime. Offenders know that there is a low chance of being apprehended; proper punishment can only occur after arrest, prosecution and trial have taken place; and so the link between the pains of imprisonment and the knife-carrying behaviour is both contingent and remote. Knife carrying is better understood as part of a problematic culture amongst certain young males, not simply an individual rational decision – and the measures that we use to address it must recognise this.
  3. Judges already have the power to sentence offenders to a prison sentence for carrying a knife and do so regularly. These amendments are therefore unnecessary.
  4. The culture of knife carrying is dangerous and undesirable, but the imposition of minimum sentences will do nothing to change this culture. It is misleading or misconceived to expect that it could. The Violence Reduction Unit promotes a public health approach to dealing with violence which is more likely to have a real impact on behaviour.